Anselm's ontological argument.
Basic bio: Anselm called
the "second Augustine." Anselm was born in NW Italy, spent much of his
life in the Norman French monastery of Bec. From 1089-death was Archbishop
of Canterbury. (1093 according to Hyman and Walsh). Hyman and Walsh cite
his response to the news of his own death as characteristic of the man:
"If it is his will I shall
gladly obey, but if He should prefer me to stay with you just long enough
to solve the question of the origin of the soul which I have been turning
over in my mind, I would gratefully accept the chance, for I doubt whether
anybody else will solve it when I'm gone." [Hyman and Walsh, p. 148, citing
M. Charlesworth, St. Anselm's P Proslogion, Oxford, 1965, p. 21.]
He is praised by Hyman and Walsh for not following the pedagogical trend
of beating students. Following Augustine, Anselm believed that reason sans
faith was worthless. But with faith, reason extremely powerful. Those with
faith can demonstrate not only existence of G, but also the incarnation,
and Trinity.
Quotes from p. 147 Hyman
and Walsh: "Ontological truth--truth of things--fulfillment of the relevant
standard or ideal". Conception of truth as rightness perceptible to the
mind alone with G as the ultimate truth."
Define ontological as of
or pertaining to being or nature.
Chapter 1, Note Bene: The
Augustinian conclusion of this chapter.
Chapter 2: The proof by
reduction that G exists. Discuss Reductio proofs.
Chapter 3: The proof by
reductio that G necessarily exists.
Chapter 4: How the fool
can deny this in his heart. One way to think a thesis T is to think the
words, the other way is to understand it and affirm it (i.e., given the
apparent Augustinian meaning of "understanding" to know it).
conclusion: EVen If Anselm
did not want to believe in G's existence, Anselm would understand it.
Gaunilo's reply on behalf
of the fool
1. Summarizes Anselm's argument
2. Reduction in reply: clearly
if to think it and affirm it is the same thing, then to think it as object
in mind is same as understanding that it exists. But it isn't. Pragmatic
criticism: if it were, the argument would not be necessary in the first
place.
3. This kind of argument
only appropriate to mental things; G is not a mental thing.
4. I don't really have the
clear concept of G, only a verbal formula. If I don't understand it, the
argument won't work. (Didn't Anselm acknowledge this?)
5. Gaunilo grants that the
concept exists in his mind . Gaunilo does not see how Anselm bridges
the gap between mental and extra-mental existence.
6. The island rejection--reduction
to foolishness.
7. Argument that Anselm
needs more argument for the concept of necessary existence of G.
8. Ends with praise
Anselm's Reply
I. We can so thus conceive
G--Anselm appeals to Gaunilo's faith and conscience. Anselm reasserts the
argument about necessary existence of G. Furthermore, G's non-existence
cannot be thought of in the same way as other entities since . . . he reasserts
the reductio regarding G.
II. Reasserts reductio.
III. regarding the island.
G is sui generis; if not, then the island ok! G, for example, has necessary
existence. DISCUSS MATERIAL OJECTS AND CONTINGENT BEINGS.
IV. "Even if none of those
things that exist can be understood not to exist, all however can
be thought as non-existing, save that which exists to the supreme
degree."
V. Anselm points out that
the greatest not equivalent for the purpose of the argument to "that than
which none greater can be conceived."
VI. I'm not clear on this
one; what do you think?
VII. IF you wish, we can
leave G's name out of it, relying on Anselm's definition to make the argument
work, making the divine connexion later.
VIII. Proof texts and experience
show we can so have this concept of "that than which none greater can be
conceived."
IX. Even if G were beyond
thought and understanding , this formula is not--just as we can speak of
the ineffable and the inconceivable.
X. Reassertion of his own
correctness and gracious praise for his critic.